Chapter 8: Rights(*)
The concept of Rights is in origin a legal concept. In fact, in
most European languages the term for Law is identical with the term for Right.
The Latin jus, the French droit, the Italian diritto, the
Spanish derecho, the German Recht signify both the legal rule that
binds a person and the legal right that every person claims as his own. These
coincidences are no mere accident. Law and Right are correlative terms. They are
two sides of the same coin. All private rights are derived from the legal order,
while the legal order involves the aggregate of all the rights coordinated by
it. As one legal writer puts it: "We can hardly define a right better than
by saying that it is the range of action assigned to a particular will within
the social order established by law." (1)
In other words, just because every person under the rule of
law is divested of an unlimited liberty of action, a certain liberty of action within
the legal limits is conceded and guaranteed to him by right.
When a man claims something as a right, he claims it as his
own or as due to him. The very conception of a legal right for one
man implies an ob4yation on the part of somebody else or of everybody
else. If a creditor has a right to a sum of money owed to him on a certain day,
the debtor has an obligation to pay it. If you have a right to freedom of
speech, to privacy, or to the ownership of a house, everyone else has an obligation
to respect it. A legal right for me implies a legal duty of others not to
interfere with my free exercise of it.
Among legal rights almost universally recognized and
protected today are the right to freedom from assault, or from arbitrary arrest
or imprisonment; the right to be protected from arbitrary intrusion into one's
home; the right to freedom of speech and publication (within certain established
limits); the right to hold property; the right to compensation for damages
inflicted by trespassers; the right to demand fulfillment of a contract; and
many others.
The notion of legal right has its counterpart in legal duty.
In their legal relations men either claim or owe. If A exerts an
acknowledged right, he has the legal power to require that B (or that B, C, D,
etc.) shall act or forbear to act in a certain way -- shall do something or abstain
from doing something.
Neither legally nor morally can "property rights" be
properly contrasted with "human rights":
The right of ownership is, strictly speaking, quite as much a
personal right -- the right of one person against other persons -- as a right to
service, or a lease. It may be convenient for certain purposes to speak of
rights over things, but in reality there can only be rights in respect of things
against persons.... Relations and intercourse arise exclusively between
live beings; but goods as well as ideas are the object and the material of such
relations; and when a right of ownership in a watch or a piece of land is
granted to me by law, this means not only that the seller has entered into a
personal obligation to deliver those things to me, but also that every person
will be bound to recognize them as mine. (2)
"Every single legal rule may be thought of as one of the
bulwarks or boundaries erected by society in order that its members shall not
collide with each other in their actions." (3) As
every legal rule appears as a necessary adjunct to some relation of social
intercourse, it is often difficult to say whether the rule precedes the rights
and duties involved in the relation, or vice versa. Both of these sides of law
stand in constant cross-relations with each other.
Constitutional Guarantees
In the last three centuries there has been an expansion of
legal rights and an increasingly explicit recognition of their existence and
importance. To protect the individual against abuses in statute law or by
law-enforcement officials, "bills of rights" have been incorporated into
written constitutions. The most famous of these is the Bill of Rights adopted in
1790 in the American Constitution.
The Bill of Rights is another name for the first ten
Amendments. It guarantees freedom of worship, of speech, and of the press; the
right of the people peaceably to assemble, and to petition the government for a
redress of grievances; the right of the people to be secure in their persons,
houses, papers, and effects, against unreasonable searches and seizures; the
right of every person not to be compelled in any criminal case to be a witness
against himself; nor to be deprived of life, liberty, or property, without due
process of law; nor to have his property taken for public use, without just
compensation; the right of the accused, in all criminal prosecutions, to a
speedy and public trial by an impartial jury; the right to be protected against
excessive bail and excessive fines, and cruel and unusual punishments.
This list is not complete. To the rights specified in the
first ten Amendments, additional rights were later added in the Fourteenth
Amendment. Some rights, in fact, are specified in the original Constitution. The
privilege of the writ of habeas coipus cannot be suspended unless in
cases of rebellion or invasion the public safety may require it. Congress is
prohibited from passing any bill of attainder or ex post facto law. Any
state also is prohibited from passing any bill of attainder, ex post facto law,
or law impairing the obligation of contracts.
We shall return later to fuller consideration of some of
these rights, and of their scope and limitations.
Natural Rights
Especially in the last two centuries, there has been a
broadening of the concept of legal rights to the notion of "natural rights."
This was already implicit and sometimes explicit, however, in the thought of
Plato and Aristotle, of Cicero and the Roman jurists, and becomes more explicit
and detailed in the writings of Locke, Rousseau, Burke, and Jefferson. (4)
The term Natural Rights, like the term Natural Law,
is in some respects unfortunate. It has helped to perpetuate a mystique which
regards such rights as having existed since the beginning of time; as having
been handed down from heaven; as being simple, self-evident, and easily stated;
as even being independent of the human will, independent of consequences,
inherent in the nature of things. This concept is reflected in the Declaration
of Independence: " We hold these truths to be self-evident, that all men
are created equal, that they are endowed by their Creator with certain
unalienable Rights, that among these are Life, Liberty, and the pursuit of
Happiness."
A Goal or Ideal
Yet though the term Natural Rights easily lends itself
to misinterpretation, the concept is indispensable; and it will do no
harm to keep the term as long as we clearly understand it to mean ideal rights,
the legal rights that every man ought to enjoy. The historic function of
the doctrine of Natural Rights has been, in fact, to insist that the individual
be guaranteed legal rights that he did not have, or held only uncertainly and
precariously.
By a further extension, we are justified in talking not only
of "natural" legal rights but of moral rights. Yet clarity of
thought demands that we hold fast to at least one part of the legal meaning
of "rights." We have seen that every right of one man implies a
corresponding
obligation of others to do something or refrain from doing something so
that he may be protected in and even guaranteed that right. If we abandon
this two-sided concept the term right becomes a mere rhetorical flourish
without definite meaning.
Pseudo-Rights
Before we examine the real nature and function of
"natural" or moral rights it will clarify our ideas to look at some
illegitimate extensions of the concept.
These have been rife for the last generation. An outstanding
example is the Four Freedoms announced by President Franklin D. Roosevelt in
1941. The first two of these -- freedom of speech and expression, and
"freedom of every person to worship God in his own way" -- are legitimate
freedoms and legitimate rights. They were, in fact, already guaranteed in the
Constitution. But the last two -- freedom from want... everywhere in the world and
"freedom from fear ... anywhere in the world" are illegitimate extensions of
the concept of freedom or the concept of rights.
It will be noticed that the first two are freedoms of (or to),
and the second two are freedoms from. Had Roosevelt used the synonym
"liberty," he would still have been able to promise "liberty to, "but
English idiom would hardly have allowed him to promise "liberty from." (5)
"Freedom to" is a guaranty that no one, including the government,
will be allowed to interfere with one's freedom of thought and
expression; but "freedom from" means that it is considered the duty of
someone else to supply one's wants or to remove one's fears.
Aside from the fact that this is a demand impossible of fulfillment (in a world
of daily dangers and in a world in which we have not collectively produced
enough to meet all our wants), just how does it become someone else's duty to
supply my wants or to banish my fears? And how do I decide just whose duty
it is?
Human Rights and the U.N.
Another outstanding example of a demand for pseudo-rights is
found in the Universal Declaration of Human Rights adopted by the General
Assembly of the United Nations in 1948. This declaration states, for example,
that "everyone has the right to rest and leisure," including reasonable
limitation of working hours and periodic holidays with pay. Assuming that this
is even possible for everyone (in South America, Asia, Africa, and in the
present state of civilization), whose obligation is it to provide all this? And
how far does each provider's alleged obligation extend?
The same questions may be asked of all the rhetorical demands
for alleged rights that we now hear almost daily -- the right to a minimum
standard of living; "the right to a decent wage;" "the right to a job;" the right to an education; and even "the right to a comfortable living;" "the right to a satisfactory job," or "the right to
a good education." It is not only that all these alleged rights have vague
quantitative boundaries -- that they do not specify how high a wage is considered
"decent" or how much education "the right to an education"
implies. What makes them pseudo-rights is that they imply that it is somebody
else's obligation to supply those things. But they do not usually tell us
whose obligation, or precisely how it comes to be his. My
"right to a job" implies that it is somebody else's duty to give me a
job, apparently regardless of my qualifications or even whether I would do more
damage than good on the job.
Absolute vs. Prima Facie Rights
Unfortunately, disposing of some of the more obviously
pseudo- rights does only a little to simplify our problem. Natural rights or
moral rights are not always self-evident, are not necessarily simple, and are
seldom if ever absolute. If legal rights are the correlates of legal rules,
moral rights are the correlates of moral rules. And as moral duties may
sometimes conflict with each other, so may moral rights. My legal and moral
rights are limited by your legal and moral rights. My right to freedom of
speech, for example, is limited by your right not to be slandered. And
"your right to swing your arm ends where my nose begins."
The temptation to simplify moral rights is great. One moral
philosopher, Hastings Rashdall, tried to reduce them all to one single right -- the
right to equality of consideration:
Not only does the principle of equal consideration not
necessarily prescribe any actual equality of Well-being or of the material
conditions of Well-being: when properly understood, it does not favor the
attempt to draw up a priori any detailed list of the "rights of man."
It is impossible to discover any tangible concrete thing, or even any specific
"Liberty" of action or acquisition, to which it can be contended that every
individual or human being has a right under all circumstances. There are
circumstances under which the satisfaction of any and every such right is a
physical impossibility. And if every assertion of right is to be conditioned by
the clause "if it be possible," we might as well boldly say that every man,
woman, and child on the earth's surface has a right to £1000 a year. There is
every bit as much reason for such an assertion as for maintaining that every one
has a right to the means of subsistence, or to three acres and a cow, or to
life, or to liberty, or to the Parliamentary franchise, or to propagate his
species, or the like. There are conditions under which none of these rights can
be given to one man without prejudice to the equal rights of others. There
seems, then, to be no "right of man" which is unconditional, except the
right to consideration -- that is to say, the right to have his true Well-being
(whatever that true Well-being be) regarded as of equal importance in all social
arrangements with the Well-being of everybody else.
Elaborate expositions of the rights of man are, at best,
attempts to formulate the most important actual or legal rights which an
application of the principle of equality would require to be conceded to the
generality of men at a particular state of social development. They are all
ultimately resolvable into the one supreme and unconditional right -- the right
to consideration; and all particular applications of that principle must be
dependent upon circumstances of time and place. (6)
A Vague Criterion
In its negative contention -- in emphasizing how many devoutly
to-be-wished-for conditions may be falsely called rights -- this passage is highly
instructive. But in its affirmative contention -- in its effort to prove that all
rights may be subsumed under equality of consideration -- the passage cannot be
called successful. No doubt "equality of consideration" is one moral
right. But it is a very vague one. Suppose we think of it for a moment as a
claimed legal right. Suppose a chair of philosophy falls vacant at
Harvard and M, N, and 0 are among those who secretly aspire to be appointed to
the post. And suppose, instead, that A gets the appointment and M, N, and 0
discover that A was, in fact, the only man even considered for the post?
How could any one of the unsuccessful hopefuls go about legally proving that
he did not get equality of consideration? (And in just what would "equality
of consideration" have consisted?) He could say that the appointing group was
influenced by irrelevant considerations -- by considerations apart from what
were strictly A's qualifications for the post -- or that his, M's, qualifications
for the post were not even considered. But could the appointing group reasonably
be expected to consider equally everybody's qualifications for the post?
Or is Rashdall's criterion merely another form of Bentham's "everybody to
count for one, nobody to count for more than one?" And just how would either
criterion help a man to decide a specific moral problem -- such as, in a ship-wreck
at sea, whether to save his wife or a stranger? Or even (if conditions made this
the only alternative) whether to save his wife or two strangers?
We must try to think of moral rights with at least as much
care and precision as legislators, judges, and jurists are compelled to think of
legal rights. We cannot be satisfied with any vague and easy rhetorical
solutions. Legal rights actually constitute an intricate and interrelated
structure of rights worked out by centuries of judicial reasoning applied to
centuries of human experience. Contrary to Justice Holmes's facile epigram:
"The life of the law has not been logic; it has been experience," (7) the life of the law has been both logic and experience. The law is
the product of logic and reason brought to bear on experience.
As everyone's rights are conditioned by the equal rights of
others, as the rights of each must be harmonized and coordinated with the equal
rights of all, and as one right may not always and everywhere be compatible with
another, there are few if any absolute rights. Even the right to life and
the right to freedom of speech are not absolute. John Locke often wrote as if
the rights to life, liberty, and property were absolute, but he made
exceptions and qualifications in the course of his discussion: "Every one
as he is bound to preserve himself... so by the like reason, when his own
preservation comes not in competition, ought he as much as he can to
preserve the rest of mankind, and not unless it be to do justice on an
offender, take away or impair the life, or what tends to the preservation of
the life, the liberty, health, limb, or goods of an other." (8) (My italics.)
Even the right to freedom of speech does not extend to libel,
slander, or obscenity (though there may be difficult problems of definition
concerning the latter). And nearly everyone will concede the limits to free
speech as defined by Justice Holmes in a celebrated opinion:
The most stringent protection of free speech would not protect a man in falsely
shouting fire in a theatre, and causing a panic. It does not even protect a man
from injunction against uttering words that may have all the effect of force.
The question in every case is whether the words are used in such circumstances
and are of such a nature as to create a clear and present danger that they will
bring about the substantive evils that Congress has a right to prevent. It is a
question of proximity and degree. (9)
Adherence to Principle the Ultimate Foundation
The suggestion has been made, following the analogy of the
concept of "prima facie duties" (which we owe to Sir David Ross), that
though we have no absolute rights, we do have prima facie rights. That is,
we have a prima facie right to life, liberty, property, etc., which must
be respected in the absence of some conflicting right or other consideration.
But just as the law must be more precise than this, so must moral philosophy.
Legal rights are of course subject to certain conditions and qualifications. But
within those necessary qualifications, legal rights are or ought to be inviolable.
And so, of course, should moral rights be inviolable.
This inviolability does not rest on some mystical yet
self-evident "law of nature." It rests ultimately (though it will shock many
to hear this) on utilitarian considerations. But it rests, not on ad hoc utilitism,
on expediency in any narrow sense, but on rule utilitism, on the
recognition that the highest and only permanent utility comes from an unyielding
adherence to principle. Only by the most scrupulous respect for each
other's imprescriptible rights can we maximize social peace, order, and
cooperation.
Notes
* This article was published in the September 1964 issue of The Freeman.
1. Paul Vinogradoff, Common-Sense in Law (Home University Library; New York: Henry Holt, 1914), pp. 61-62. I am indebted to Vinogradoff's whole discussion of the nature of rights in positive law.
2. Ibid., pp, 68-69.
3. mid., p. 70.
4. A scholarly and illuminating history can be found in Leo Strauss, Natural Right and History (University of Chicago Press. 1953).
5. See George Santayana, Dominations and Powers (New York: Scribner's, 1951 ), p. 58n.
6. The Theory of Good and Evil (Oxford University Press, 1907), p. 1,227.
7. Justice Oliver Wendell Holmes, Jr. The Common Law (1881).
8. Two Treatises of Civil Government (1689), Book II, Chap. 2, sec. 6.
9. Schenck v. United States, 249 U.S. 52.
"Wisdom of Henry Hazlitt" Home Page |
Next Chapter
This e-text is made available by The Henry Hazlitt Foundation in cooperation with The Foundation for Economic Education. The Hazlitt Foundation is a member-supported 501(c)(3) non-profit corporation whose mission is to make the ideas of freedom more accessible. Please visit our flagship Internet service Free-Market.Net: The world's most comprehensive source for information on liberty.
© 19XX. For permissions information, contact The Foundation for Economic Education, 30 South Broadway, Irvington-on-Hudson, NY 10533.
The Henry Hazlitt Foundation
Jamie Hazlitt
45 Division St
S1 4GE Sheffield, UK
+44 114 275 6539
contact@hazlitt.org, /
|