This e-text of Henry Hazlitt's 1964 "The Foundations of Morality" is made available by the The Henry Hazlitt Foundation in cooperation with The Foundation for Economic Education. The Hazlitt Foundation is a member-supported 501(c)(3) non-profit corporation whose mission is to make the ideas of freedom more accessible. Please visit our flagship Internet service Free-Market.Net: The world's most comprehensive source for information on liberty. | |
Chapter 4: Pleasure as the End
The doctrine that pleasure is the sole ultimate good, and pain
the sole evil, is at least as old as Epicurus (341-270 B.C.).
But the doctrine, from the beginning, has been denounced as heretical
by the bulk of orthodox or ascetic moralists -- so much so, that
it almost disappeared until it was revived in the seventeenth
and eighteenth centuries. The writer who then stated it in its
most uncompromising, elaborate, and systematic form was Jeremy
Bentham. (1)
If we may judge by the number of references to him and his doctrines
in the literature of the subject, even though most of them are
critical, angry, or derisive, Bentham has been the most discussed
and influential moralist of modern times. It seems profitable,
therefore, to begin with an analysis of the hedonistic doctrine
as he states it.
His best known (as well as his most authentic) (2) statement is
in his Principles of Morals and Legislation. The paragraphs
with which he opens that book are bold and sweeping.
"Nature has placed mankind under the governance of two sovereign
masters, pain and pleasure. It is for them alone
to point out what we ought to do, as well as to determine what
we shall do. On the one hand the standard of right and wrong,
on the other hand the chain of causes and effects, are fastened
to their throne. They govern us in all we do, in all we say, in
all we think: every effort we can make to throw off our subjection,
will serve but to demonstrate and confirm it. In words a man may
pretend to abjure their empire: but in reality he will remain
subject to it all the while. The principle of utility recognizes
this subjection, and assumes it for the foundation of that system,
the object of which is to rear the fabric of felicity by the hands
of reason and law. Systems which attempt to question it, deal
in sounds instead of sense, in caprice instead of reason, in darkness
instead of light."
It will be noticed that in the second sentence of this paragraph
Bentham draws no distinction whatever between what has since come
to be known as the doctrine of psychological hedonism (the
doctrine that we always do take the action which we think will
give us the greatest pleasure) and the doctrine that has come
to be known as ethical hedonism (the doctrine that we ought
to take the action which will result in the greatest pleasure
or happiness). But we may leave the disentanglement of this knotty
problem to a later chapter.
Bentham goes on to explain that: "The principle of utility is the foundation of the present work. By the principle of utility is meant that principle which approves or disapproves of every action whatsoever, according to the tendency which it appears to have to augment or diminish the happiness of the party whose interest is in question .... I say of every action whatsoever; and therefore not only of every action of a private individual, but of every measure of government." By utility is meant that property in any object, whereby it tends to produce benefit, advantage, pleasure, good, or happiness (all this in the present case comes to the same thing), or (what comes again to the same thing) to prevent the happening of mischief, pain, evil, or unhappiness to the party whose interest is considered: if that party be the community in general, then the happiness of the community: if a particular individual, then the happiness of that Individual. (3)
Bentham later modified his ideas, or at least their expression.
He acknowledged his debt for the "principle of utility"
to Hume, but came to find the principle too vague. Utility for
what end? Bentham took over from an essay on Government by Priestley
in 1768 the phrase "the greatest happiness of the greatest
number" but later substituted both for this and for "utility"
the Greatest Happiness Principle. Increasingly, too (as revealed
in the Deontology) he substituted "happiness"
and "greatest happiness" for "pleasure," and
in the Deontology he arrived at the definition: "Morality
is the art of maximizing happiness: it gives the code of laws
by which that conduct is suggested whose result will, the whole
of human existence being taken into account, leave the greatest
quantity of felicity." (4)
2. The Charge of Sensuality
It is against the statement of his theory in the form found in
his Morals and Legislation, however (and against popular
misconceptions of what he believed or continued to believe),
that the great storm of criticism has been directed.
As the primary purpose of these early chapters will be to lay
the foundation for a positive theory of morals, I shall here discuss
only a few of the respects in which that criticism was either
valid or unjustified; and I shall discuss them, not so much as
they apply to the specific doctrines of Bentham, but to hedonistic
or eudaemonic doctrines in general.
The most frequent objection to hedonism or utilitarianism on the
part of anti-hedonist and anti-utilitarian writers is that the
"pleasure" which it makes the goal of action refers
to a purely physical or sensual pleasure. Thus Schumpeter
calls it "the shallowest of all conceivable philosophies
of life," and insists that the "pleasure" it talks
of is merely the pleasure epitomized in eating beefsteaks. (5) And
moralists like Carlyle have not hesitated to call it a "pig
philosophy." This criticism is immemorial. "Epicurean"
has become a synonym for a sensualist, and the followers of Epicurus
have been condemned as the "swine" of Epicurus.
Closely allied to this criticism, and sharing almost equal prominence
with it, is the accusation that hedonism and utilitarianism preach
essentially the philosophy of sensuality and self-indulgence,
the philosophy of the voluptuary and the libertine.
Now while it is true that there are people who both practice and
preach the philosophy of sensuality, it receives very little support
from Bentham -- or, for that matter, from any of the leading utilitarians.
So far as the charge of sensuality is concerned, no one who has
ever read Bentham can have any excuse for making it. (6) For in
his elaborate enumeration and classification of "pleasures,"
he lists not only the pleasures of sense, in which he includes
the pleasure of health, and the pleasures of wealth and power,
including those both of acquisition and of possession, but the
pleasures of memory and imagination, or association and expectation,
and the pleasures of amity, of a good name, of piety, and of benevolence
or good will. (He is also realistic and candid enough to list
the pleasures of malevolence or ill will.) And when he comes to the question of how a pleasure should be measured, valued, or compared, he lists seven criteria or "circumstances":
The foregoing quotations do, I think, point to some of the real
shortcomings in Bentham's analysis. These include his failure
to construct a convincing "hedonistic calculus" (though
his elaborate effort to do so was itself highly instructive).
They include his tendency to treat "pleasure" or "pain"
as something that can be abstracted and isolated from specific
pleasures or pains and treated like a physical or chemical residue,
or like a homogeneous juice that can be quantitatively measured.
I will return to these points later. Here I wish to point out
that Bentham and the utilitarians generally cannot be justly accused
of assigning to "pleasure" a purely sensual meaning.
Nor does their emphasis on promoting pleasure and avoiding pain
necessarily lead to a philosophy of self-indulgence. The critics
of hedonism or utilitarianism constantly talk as if its votaries
measured all pleasures merely in terms of their intensity.
But the key words in Bentham's comparisons are duration,
fecundity, and purity. And the greatest of these is
duration. In discussing the virtue of "self-regarding
prudence," Bentham constantly emphasizes the importance of
not sacrificing the future to the present, the importance of giving
"preference to the greater future over the less present pleasure.
(8) "Is not temperance a virtue? Aye, assuredly is it. But
wherefore? Because by restraining enjoyment for a time, it afterwards
elevates it to that very pitch which leaves, on the whole, the
largest addition to the stock of happiness." (9)
3. Of the Greatest Number
Bentham's views have been misunderstood in another important respect-though
this is in large part his own fault. One of the phrases he is
thought to have originated-which was once most often quoted with
approval by his disciples but is now the most frequent target
for his critics-is "the greatest happiness of the greatest
number." But first, as we have seen, this was not Bentham's
original phrase, but taken by him from Priestley (who was in turn
anticipated both by Hutcheson and Beccaria); and secondly, Bentham
himself later abandoned it. When he did reject it he did so with
a clearer and more powerful argument (so far as it goes) than
any I have seen by any critic. It is quoted by Bowring in the
final pages of the first volume of the posthumous Deontology,
from which I paraphrase it: "The principle of the Greatest Happiness of the Greatest Number is questionable because it can be interpreted as ignoring the feelings or fate of the minority. And this questionableness becomes greater the greater we conceive the ratio to be of the minority to the majority."
Let us suppose a community of 4001 persons of which the
"majority" numbers 2001 and the minority 2000. Suppose that,
to begin with, each of the 4001 possesses an equal portion of
happiness. If, now, we take his share of happiness from every
one of the 2000 and divide it among the 2001, the result would
be, not an augmentation, but a vast diminution of happiness. The
feelings of the minority being, according to the "greatest
number" principle, left out of account, the vacuum thus left,
instead of remaining a vacuum, may be filled with the greatest
unhappiness and suffering. The net result for a whole community
would not be a gain in happiness but a great loss.
Or assume, again, that your 4001 persons are at the outset
in a state of perfect equality with respect to the means to happiness,
including power and opulence, with every one possessing not only
equal wealth, but equal liberty and independence. Now take your
2000, or no matter how much smaller a minority, reduce
them to a state of slavery, and divide them and their former property
among the 2001. How many in the community will actually
have their happiness increased? What would be the result for the
happiness of the whole community? The questions answer themselves.
To make the application more specific, Bentham then went on to
ask what would happen if, in Great Britain, the whole body of
the Roman Catholics were made slaves and divided among the whole
body of Protestants, or if, in Ireland, the whole body of Protestants
were divided, in like manner, among the whole body of Roman Catholics.
So Bentham fell back on the Greatest Happiness Principle, and
spoke of the goal of ethics as that of maximizing the happiness
of the community as a whole.
4. "Pleasure" vs. "Happiness"
This statement of the ultimate criterion of moral rules leaves
many troublesome questions unanswered. We may postpone consideration
of some of these to a later point, but we can hardly escape dealing
with a few of them now, if our answer is to be even provisionally
satisfactory. Some of these questions are perhaps purely semantic
or linguistic; others are psychological or philosophical; and
in some cases it is difficult to determine whether we are in fact
dealing with a verbal or a psychological or a moral problem.
This applies especially to the use of the terms pleasure and
pain. Bentham himself, as we have seen, who originally
made the systematic use of these terms basic to his ethical system,
later tended to abandon the term pleasure more and more
for the term happiness. But he insisted to the end that:
"Happiness is the aggregate of which pleasures are the component
parts. . . . Let not the mind be led astray by any distinctions
drawn between pleasures and happiness .... Happiness without
pleasures is a chimera and a contradiction; it is a million without
any units, a square yard in which there shall be no inches, a
bag of guineas without an atom of gold." (10)
The conception of happiness as a mere arithmetical summation of
units of pleasure and pain, however, finds little acceptance today,
either by moral philosophers, psychologists, or the man in the
street. And persistent difficulties are presented by the words
pleasure and pain. It is in vain that some moral
philosophers have warned that they should be used and understood
only in a purely formal sense. The popular association of
these words with merely sensual and carnal pleasure is so strong
that such a warning is certain to be forgotten. Meanwhile antihedonists
consciously or unconsciously make full use of this association
to deride and discredit the utilitarian writers who use the words.
It seems the part of practical wisdom, and the best way to minimize
misunderstanding, to use the terms "pleasure" and "pain"
very sparingly, if not to abandon them almost altogether in ethical
discussion.
1. Bentham's ethical theories are presented chiefly in A Fragment on Government (1776), An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation (printed in 1780 but not published until 1789), and the posthumous Deontology, edited from manuscripts by Bowring in 1834. For a full exposition and critique of Bentham's ethical writings, as well as a history of his reputation, see David Baumgardt, Bentham and the Ethics of Today (Princeton University Press, 1952). 2. In the posthumous Deontology, which Bowring claims to have "put together" from "disjointed fragments, written on small scraps of paper, on the spur of the moment, at times remote from one another, and delivered into my hands without order or arrangement of any sort" it is difficult to tell what is Bentham's from what is Bowring's. 3. Morals and Legislation, p. 2. 5. Joseph A. Schumpeter, History of Economic Analysis (New York: Oxford University Press, 1954), p. 131 et al. 6. John Hospers has shown that the charge is unjust even as directed against the actual doctrines of Epicurus. See "Epicureanism," Human Conduct (Harcourt, Brace, 1961), pp. 49-59. 7. Morals and Legislation, p. 30. 11. See Ludwig von Mises, Human Action (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1949), pp. 14-15, and Theory and History (Yale, 1957), pp. 12-13n. Also Ludwig Feuerbach, Eudamonismus, in "Sammtliche Werke," ed. Bolin and Jodl (Stuttgart, 1907, 10, 230-93. Further sources of confusion are pointed out by John Hospers in Human Conduct, esp. pp. 111-116. These include the confusion of "pleasure" in the sense of a source of pleasure, such as a pleasurable sensation, with pleasure in the sense of a pleasant state of consciousness. It is the opposite of the first only that can properly be described as "pain," whereas the true opposite of the second is displeasure. The failure to make this distinction was a major source of confusion in Bentham and Mill. © 1964 Henry Hazlitt. For permissions information, contact The Foundation for Economic Education, 30 South Broadway, Irvington-on-Hudson, NY 10533. Jamie Hazlitt 45 Division St S1 4GE Sheffield, UK +44 114 275 6539 contact@hazlitt.org, / |