This e-text of Henry Hazlitt's 1964 "The Foundations of Morality" is made available by the The Henry Hazlitt Foundation in cooperation with The Foundation for Economic Education. The Hazlitt Foundation is a member-supported 501(c)(3) non-profit corporation whose mission is to make the ideas of freedom more accessible. Please visit our flagship Internet service Free-Market.Net: The world's most comprehensive source for information on liberty. | |
Chapter 12: Prudence and Benevolence
Nowhere is a more logical, better-organized, or more stimulating
discussion of private ethics to be found than in the two volumes
of Jeremy Bentham's Deontology: or The Science of Morality.
Yet these two volumes have had an unfortunate history. They
were published posthumously, in 1834. They do not profess to be
wholly by Bentham, even on their title page. That title page is
for several reasons worth quoting in full: "Deontology:
or The Science of Morality: in which the harmony and coincidence
of Duty and Self-Interest, Virtue and Felicity, Prudence and Benevolence,
are explained and exemplified. From the MSS. of Jeremy Bentham.
Arranged and Edited by John Bowring." The whole of Bentham's work, partly because of its sheer range
and mass, partly because of its stylistic eccentricities, partly
because of his own carelessness and indifference regarding publication,
and his refusal to do his own revision and editing of most of
his manuscripts, has lain in comparative neglect until recently.
Though his influence has been enormous, it has been mainly indirect,
through Dumont, John Austin, James Mill, and above all John Stuart
Mill. Yet the neglect of the Deontology has exceeded even
the general neglect of Bentham's work. It has been considered
of doubtful authenticity. It has been suspected that much was
filled in between Bentham's notes by his editor Bowring. Whatever
the truth may be, the greater part of the book seems to me to
show the hand of the master.
The purpose of this chapter is primarily, taking off from the
presentation in Bentham's Deontology, to discuss the "harmony
and coincidence" of Prudence and Benevolence. But because
the Deontology has been out of print since its original
edition, and because the volumes in the original are very difficult
to come by, I shall give a somewhat wider summary of their contents
than would otherwise be warranted merely by a discussion of the
relations between Prudence and Benevolence. The Deontology opens with a general statement of the utilitarian
theme, seeking to emphasize "the alliance between interest
and duty." "To a great extent ... the dictates of
prudence prescribe the laws of effective benevolence .... A
man who injures himself more than he benefits others by no means
serves the cause of virtue, for he diminishes the amount of happiness"
(1, 177). "Prudence is man's primary virtue. Nothing is gained
to happiness if prudence loses more than benevolence wins"
(1, 189-90).
Bentham contends that "prudence and effective benevolence
... being the only two intrinsically useful virtues, all other
virtues must derive their value from them, and be subservient
to them" (1, 201). He seeks to apply this standard systematically
to the virtues mentioned by Hume -- to sociability, good nature,
humanity, mercy, gratitude, friendliness, generosity, beneficence,
justice, discretion, industry, frugality, honesty, fidelity, truth
(veracity and sincerity), caution, enterprise, assiduity, economy,
sobriety, patience, constancy, perseverance, forethought, considerateness,
cheerfulness, dignity, courage, tranquillity, politeness, wit,
decency, cleanliness, chastity, and allegiance.
Bentham rightly points out that Hume's list of virtues is unsystematic,
disorderly, and disjointed; that many of them overlap and others
are merely different names for the same thing. Nor does he find
that all of them deserve the name of virtue. "Courage,"
he declares courageously, "may be a virtue or may be a vice.
... For a man to value himself on his courage, without any reference
to the occasions on which it is exercised, is to value himself
on a quality possessed in a far higher degree by a dog, especially
if the dog is mad" (1, 251). Bentham even writes a chapter on what he calls "False Virtues," among which he lists Contempt for Riches (sarcastic paragraphs directed against Socrates and Epictetus), Love of Action, Attention, Enterprise, and Dispatch. At all points he warns:
In the second volume (which is surprisingly self-contained and
complete in itself) Bentham (1) opens again with an Introduction
and "General Statement" of general principles. Here
we find him shifting from the emphasis on "pleasures"
and "pains" in his Introduction to the Principles
of Morals and Legislation to an almost exclusive reference
to the effect of conduct on "happiness" and "misery."
While he still rejects "any distinctions drawn between pleasures
and happiness," while he still insists that "happiness
is the aggregate of which pleasures are the component parts"
(11, 16), the shift is none the less significant. Bentham seems
eager to prevent the accusation or misunderstanding that he is
concerned purely with physical or sensual pleasures and pains.
But he retains the essentials of his "hedonistic calculus."
The inquiries of the moralist, he contends, may in the abstract ... be reduced to a single inquiry. At what cost of future pain or sacrifice of future pleasure is a present pleasure purchased?
What repayment of future pleasure may be anticipated for a present
pain? Out of this examination morality must be developed. Temptation
is the present pleasure-punishment is the future pain; sacrifice
is the present pain-enjoyment is the future recompense. The questions
of virtue and vice are, for the most part, reduced to the weighing
of that which is, against that which will be. The virtuous
man has a store of happiness in coming time, the vicious man has
prodigally spent his revenues of happiness. Today the vicious
man seems to have a balance of pleasure in his favor; tomorrow
the balance will be adjusted, and the day after it will be ascertained
to be wholly in favor of the virtuous man. Vice is a spendthrift,
flinging away what is far better than wealth, or health, or youth,
or beauty -- namely, happiness: because all of these without happiness
are of little value. Virtue is a prudent economist that gets back
all her outlay with interest (11, 27-8).
"Morality," continues Bentham, "is the art of maximizing
happiness: it gives the code of laws by which that conduct is
suggested whose result will, the whole of human existence being
taken into account, leave the greatest quantity of felicity"
(11, 31).
2. How Prudence Leads ...
Bentham proceeds to reduce the virtues to two, Prudence and Effective
Benevolence, but he divides each of these, respectively, into
Self-Regarding Prudence and Extra-Regarding Prudence and into
Negative Efficient Benevolence and Positive Efficient Benevolence,
and devotes a long separate chapter to each of these four divisions.
On these four cornerstones Bentham builds his palace of morality.
He is concerned to show that each one of these virtues leads naturally
and almost inevitably into the next. He begins with Self-Regarding
Prudence, which refers to actions whose influences do not reach
beyond the actor; he moves next to "that prudence which is
demanded from him in consequence of his intercourse with others;
a prudence which is closely connected with benevolence, and especially
with abstential benevolence" (11, 81).
As regards external actions, "what prudence can do, and all
that prudence can do, is to choose between the present and the
future; and in so far as the aggregate of happiness is increased,
thereby to give preference to the greater future over the lesser
present pleasure" (11, 82). But, he warns, the sacrifice
of an immediate pleasure that does not promise to increase our
own or somebody else's future happiness to an amount greater than
that immediately sacrificed "is mere asceticism; it is the
very opposite of prudence; it is the offspring of delusion";
it is "folly"; it is not virtue, it is vice (11, 34).
Bentham then shows the application of the dictates of self regarding
prudence to sexual morality: "The option is often between
the enjoyment of a moment and the pain of years; between the excited
satisfaction of a very short period and the sacrifice of a whole
existence; between the stimulation of life for an hour, and the
consequent adjacency of disease and death" (11, 85).
After rejecting asceticism as applied to sexual morality, Bentham
asks: "Is not chastity, then, a virtue? Most undoubtedly,
and a virtue of high deserving. And why? Not because it diminishes,
but because it heightens enjoyment.... In fact, temperance, modesty,
chastity, are among the most efficient sources of delight"
(11, 87-88). He proceeds to apply the same standards in discussing
why intoxication, irascibility, gambling, and extravagance tend
to produce in the long run more misery than happiness to the person
who indulges in them.
We come next to Bentham's chapter on "Extra-Regarding Prudence."
Of man's pleasures, a great proportion is dependent on the will
of others, and can only be possessed by him with their concurrence
and co-operation. There is no possibility of disregarding the
happiness of others without, at the same time, risking happiness
of our own. There is no possibility of avoiding those inflictions
of pain with which it is in the power of others to visit us, except
by conciliating their good will. Each individual is linked to
his race by a tie, of all ties the strongest, the tie of self-regard
(11, 132-3).
Morality can be nothing but the sacrifice of a lesser for the
acquisition of a greater good. The virtue of extra-regarding prudence
is only limited by our intercourse with our fellow men; it may
even extend far beyond the bounds of our personal communion with
others, by secondary, or reflected influences.... Both national
and international law may be said to constitute a proper ground
for the introduction of that prudence which concerns others (11,
135).
In our relations with others, prudence no less than benevolence
suggests the two simple precepts: "Maximize good, minimize
evil" (11, 164). Hence the rules of good manners; the rule
of sparing our neighbor's feelings; the rule of avoiding the ill
will and cultivating the good will of others towards us.
3. To Benevolence
Just as self-regarding prudence must lead us to be considerate
and kind to others, because our own happiness depends on their
good will towards us or at least the absence of their ill will,
so this extra-regarding prudence leads on in turn to "Negative
Efficient Benevolence." "A due regard to the felicity
of others is the best and wisest provision for our own" (11,
190). The first requirement is to avoid doing evil to others.
Never do evil to any other except in so far as that may be necessary
to accomplish a greater good. Never do evil to any other solely
on the ground that it is "deserved," but only if this
is unavoidable to accomplish a greater good. Even in sport or
as a joke, say nothing and do nothing that will cause uneasiness
to another. The justifications for inflicting pain on others by
your discourse are seldom tenable. "Remember, on all occasions,
that kind costs a man no more than unkind language" (11,
217). Blame nobody except to prevent some future cause of blame.
Never do or say anything to wound or humiliate another. Bentham comes next to his chapter on "Positive Efficient Benevolence." (He draws a frequent distinction between benevolence, or the disposition and desire to do good for others, and beneficence, which is the actual doing of such good, and insists that any truly moral action must be both benevolent and beneficent.) He begins by pointing out the strong prudential reasons which a man has for the exercise of benevolence:
In illustrating the requirements of beneficence, Bentham applies
in the ethical field the same lesson he had applied in the legal
field in his Principles of Morals and Legislation: In the application of evil for the production of good, never let it be applied for the gratification of mere antipathy; never but as subservient to and necessary for the only proper ends of punishment, the determent of others by example, the determent of the offenders by suffering. In the interest of the offender, reformation is the great object to be aimed at; if this cannot be accomplished, seek to disable him from inflicting the like evil on himself or others. But always bear in mind the maxim, which cannot be repeated too often: Inflict as much and no more pain than is necessary to accomplish the purpose of benevolence. Create not evil greater than the evil you exclude (11, 266-267). 4. No Exact Dividing Line Bentham returns to a discussion of the relations between prudence
and benevolence: It is not always possible to draw the exact line between the claims of efficient benevolence, whether positive or negative, and those of prudence, self-regarding or extra-regarding; nor is it always necessary or desirable, for where the interests of the two virtues are the same, the path of duty is quite clear. But points of agreement and of difference may be easily pointed out, and a general definition may show what, in ordinary cases, is the distinction between the two qualities. As for example: you are called upon to do service to another. If he is in a condition to render you services in return, prudence as well as benevolence combine to interest you in his favor. If he is wholly removed from the occasions of serving you, your motives can be those of benevolence alone. But because Bentham so often insists that the roots of benevolence
are to be ultimately found in self-regarding prudence, it is a
mistake to assume that he ever disparages benevolence. On the
contrary, his pages are full of such passages as this: To give exercise, influence, and extension to efficient benevolence, is one of the great consequences of virtue. Nor let it be thought that such benevolence is to be bounded in its consequences by the race of man .... Let men remember that happiness, wherever it is, and by whomever experienced, is the great gift confided to their charge.
We need to forward virtue not merely by our actions, but through the judicious use of our approval and disapproval: To that end we must labor, each for himself, and as far as he is able, marking out for his highest approbation in the conduct of others those actions which have produced, or are likely to produce, the greatest sum of happiness, and visiting with his loudest reprobation that conduct which leads to, or creates, the greatest amount of misery. By this means every man will do something to make the popular sanctions more useful, healthful, active, and virtuous. The alliances of true morality with the great interests of mankind man kind will soon discover (11, 274). In his concluding chapter, Bentham tells us that reason and morality
themselves must be made subservient to the great end of promoting
human happiness. "Virtue is made up of pleasures, vice of
pains, and ... morality is but the maximization of happiness"
(11, 309). 5. The Role of Sympathy I have been quoting from Bentham's (out-of-print) Deontology
at this great length, not only because of the brilliant light
it throws on the necessary relations of prudence and beneficence,
but because it develops the Greatest Happiness Principle with
more thoroughness and logic than any other work with which I am
acquainted. By identifying morality not with a pointless "will
to refrain" or self-sacrifice, but with the maximization
of happiness, and by emphasizing the essential harmony between
self-interest and the general interest, Bentham provides a far
greater incentive to morality than the conventional moralist.
His detractors, from Matthew Arnold to Karl Marx, have always
been fond of dismissing him as crass and vulgar, but he is as
superior to them in the breadth of his sympathies as he is in
analysis and logic.
This is not to say that his discussion is definitive or lacking
in faults. He too often assumes, for example, that an action can
be taken on a direct calculation of the happiness or misery that
would follow from that action considered in isolation. He failed
to grasp the full weight of Hume's principle that we must inflexibly
act according to rule, and that it is the goodness or badness
of the rules of moral action, the tendency of the moral
code to produce happiness or unhappiness, that is to be
judged, rather than the assumed consequences of an isolated individual
act.
There is also implicit in Bentham's discussion the assumption
that benevolence can only grow out of enlightened and farseeing
prudence. Most benevolence is, in fact, direct; it is the result
of an immediate and spontaneous affection, love, kindness, or
sympathy, a fellow-feeling with others (a theme that Hume and
Adam Smith had developed), and not of any conscious calculation
that its benefits will redound to the future advantage of the
agent himself. The Biblical injunction, "Cast thy bread upon
the waters: for thou shalt find it after many days," implies,
as Bentham does, that charity and other acts of benevolence will
ultimately redound to the benefit of the one who performs them;
but it implies, in addition, that the repayment is not necessarily
dependable or proportional.
Yet Bentham was right in recognizing the essential long-run
harmony between self-interest and the general interest, between
the actions prescribed by "prudence" and the actions
prescribed by "benevolence," between farsighted "egoism"
and farsighted "altruism." And the recognition of this
essential long-run harmony will be found to be the basis for solving
one of the central problems of ethics -- the true relations of "egoism" and "altruism," and the relative roles that each should properly play.
1. Perhaps I should write Bentham-Bowring; for Bowring tells us, in a separate preface of three pages, that: "The materials out of which this volume has been put together are, for the most part, disjointed fragments, written on small scraps of paper, on the spur of the moment, at times remote from one another, and delivered into my hands without order or arrangement of any sort." The book, then, is probably at least a sort of collaboration; yet as the greater part of the reasoning and phrasing seem to me to be authentically Bentham's, I think we are justified in referring the work to him if he were the sole author. In this second volume, even more than in the first, it is instructive to notice that Bentham shies away a little from the name Utilitarianism that he himself coined to describe his doctrine in its original form. At several points he gives reasons for regarding the term as inadequate and too vague. Though he does not suggest a substitute name (except, occasionally, "the Greatest Happiness Principle"), I think he would have finally come to call his doctrine Felicitism. © 1964 Henry Hazlitt. For permissions information, contact The Foundation for Economic Education, 30 South Broadway, Irvington-on-Hudson, NY 10533. Jamie Hazlitt 45 Division St S1 4GE Sheffield, UK +44 114 275 6539 contact@hazlitt.org, / |